Sample
Final Exam
submissions 2013

(2013 final exam assignment)

LITR 5831 World Literature


Colonial-Postcolonial

 

Gregory Buchanan 

11 December 2013

Global Identity Answers Dialectical Synthesis

Alfred North Whitehead famously commented that all Western philosophy can be considered a series of footnotes to Plato. And among the Greeks, Plato was not unique in considering the polis to be the social institution most directly responsible for preserving individual freedom. Most Americans are aware, if only vaguely, of the Platonic intellectual tradition from which they inherit their belief in the primacy of the political state. Course objective three identifies the problem that many Americans have interacting with colonial-postcolonial discourse. Because the international relationship between colonizing and colonized governments defies the paradigm of localized, autonomous government with which Americans are familiar, colonization and postcolonialism seem foreign. Over the course of the semester, I used the Self-Other model of dialectical synthesis to study colonial-postcolonial problems of identity. Attempts to reconcile disparate cultural identities met with limited success in my mid-term examination and research paper. Now at the end of the semester, I realize that producing a synthesis between the colonizer and colonized is not the ideal method of arriving at viable postcolonial identity. Abandoning the traditional paradigm of the polis to embrace cosmopolitan identity seems a surer method of incorporating previously colonized countries, former colonizers, and the rest of the world into cooperative political identification. A global model of identity would operate by identifying all cultural values as equally belonging to one “domestic,” world-wide identity, creating a single world-polis and eliminating the concepts of “foreignness” and the Other. Several course texts support cosmopolitanism, yet others raise significant moral questions that must be addressed if abusive power-relations implicit in false syntheses are to be avoided. The most important question is how cosmopolitan ethics can answer the question of social progress, which seems to operate through the subordination of certain cultural values. Recognizing the necessity of global identity is the principal truth I have learned from the course. 

Upon reviewing my mid-term examination and research submission, I realized that the Self-Other model cannot fairly or accurately resolve cultural differences supported by abusive power-relations.  The Self-Other model resists a global model of identity because it attempts to produce a synthesis through reconciling difference, a dynamic concept that fails to conform to the static identity demanded by cosmopolitanism. In my mid-term examination, I listed four impediments to true synthesis between Self and Other. Oppression operates through mutually detrimental power-relations that sometimes include appropriation of technology by colonizer and the colonized: “Appropriation of technology inhibits cultural exchange for both the colonizer and the colonized through a confusion of values” (3). In George Orwell’s “Shooting an Elephant,” the protagonist is compelled to shoot what is simultaneously technology for the colonized people of India and an aesthetic symbol of colonization from the perspective of the colonizer. The elephant represents a fundamental disconnect between two cultural worlds; their vastly different perceptions of the elephant’s cultural status and purpose signify the striking contrast that the concept of difference can project even onto a mundane object. Political power-relations underpin these radical differences in value-orientation. The colonizers and colonized perceive the elephant differently, each group privileges its perception of the elephant over that of the other group, and they use political power (more specifically, solidarity, in the case of the colonized) to insist on the superiority of their perception. 

To reconcile cultural difference between colonizing countries and colonizers, the power-relations that support value-oriented claims of privileged difference must be understood and dissolved. This requires that they be accurately identified. Postcolonial feminism has developed a method that has the potential to do so, yet further development is required to ensure its complete accuracy. In my research submission, I examined intersectional analysis as a vehicle of ascertaining the nature of abusive power-relations within the contexts of familial and sexual expectations Jasmine and Lucy experience.  Much insight can be gleaned from treating oppression of Self and Other as a whole, but cases within the traditional categories of oppression are sometimes difficult to sort out. An intracategorical method of analysis must be employed to ensure complete fairness. My conclusion in the research submission expresses the position of intracategorical difference in postcolonial feminist scholarship: “Intracategorical analysis is a much-needed advance in understanding intersectional identity that little feminist research supports” (19). Because the Self-Other model cannot resolve the political power-relations that privilege differences of value, I believe its capacity to produce a genuine synthesis between cultural identities has yet to be realized. 

An alternative model of postcolonial identity should be able to encompass a plurality of cultural identities while avoiding the problem of power-relations. Cosmopolitan ethics, which posits global identity as the equivalent of a dialectical synthesis among all world-cultures, amalgamates the traditional categories of oppression into a harmonious system of cultural plurality. Instead of needing to examine the exact relations of oppression, as postcolonial feminism may with intracategorical difference, cosmopolitanism adopts an anticategorical approach, so it subsumes opposition into a general concept of non-identity. Oppression is still acknowledged, but it is placed outside of the value-systems of every culture in the world. This makes the idea of “superior” difference impossible. If there were an Other in cosmopolitan system of ethics, it would be the proclivity of every Self to privilege its own value-orientations. Because oppressive power-relations are at the base of claims of identity-difference, their exclusion would eliminate competitive claims of values. Difference itself would be universal and therefore static.  This means that different cultures could not oppose values, such as the aesthetic and the technological, and apply them to the same object, such as an elephant. In a 2009 final exam, Allen Reid observes the incompatibility of cultural pluralism with the Self-Other model: “When [Jasmine] arrives in America we see the idea of the ‘other’ is not a binary system; e.g., when she first arrives in Florida she is not American, ergo, she is the ‘other,’ but she is not the only ‘other’ there.  She was among many immigrants from different parts of the world” (2).  As Reid points out, the Other is not a collective identity. There are “many” Others that each engage in reciprocal relationships of otherness among themselves. Cosmopolitan ethics avoids having to synthesize every constituent Other and instead assumes a global Self. 

Course texts and objectives support the project of global identity, especially as it relates to the concept of place. Objective six describes attachment to place in relation to global culture, stating that modern cultures tend to view place in terms of amorphous space, while traditional cultures attribute significance to place. However, first-world, modern cultures consider place to substantially influence identity. This is an extension of the primacy of the political state in the Western intellectual tradition. Cosmopolitan ethics would create a global sense of belonging, or oikeiôsis, that many people presently experience through national citizenship or extended family. Derek Walcott in “The Season of Phantasmal Peace” imagines “the huge net of the shadows of this earth / in multitudinous dialects, twittering tongues, / stitching and crossing it” (2-4). The net comes to envelop the whole world, “like the vines of an orchard” (17), suggesting a universal interconnectedness. Dialectical synthesis of world cultures cannot readily produce the vision of unity Walcott imagines, offering instead only a divided world of deeply rooted power-relations. In “Passage to India,” Walt Whitman also expounds a vision of global unity. “All these separations and gaps shall be taken up and hook’d and / link’d together / The whole earth, this cold, impassive, voiceless earth, shall be / completely Justified” (5. 36-19). Although Whitman wrote in response to a scientific and technological advance, the opening of the Suez Canal, he explicitly praises the unification of the cultural values of the earth into a common song: “Finally shall come the poet worth that name, / The true son of God shall come singing his songs” (5. 30-31). His vision, like Walcott’s, looks forward to the adoption of global identity, as opposed to the traditional place-oriented model. 

Global identity would solve many of the problems that arise from the meeting of cultures. The idea of universal belonging associated with cosmopolitanism carries with it a rudimentary notion of justice. Its origins in ancient Greece confirm this, as Zeno of Citium, the first scholarch of the Stoic school, frequently said that universal belonging is the beginning of justice. In Chinua Achebe’s Things Fall Apart, the legal system of Umuofia relies on ancient traditions that differ from those of the colonizing government. A group of tribal egwugwu judge cases according to ancient customs, which outside governments cannot access. When the colonizing government makes a decision about a land case, it does so without consulting the traditional customs. Okonkwo protests: “Does the white man understand our custom about land?” Okonkwo is later told that the colonizers view the customs of Umuofia as immoral (176). This is an example of the privileging of difference that troubles the Self-Other model of dialectical synthesis. The colonizing government prefers its interpretation of justice because it has political power. It uses its power to impose its standard of justice on Umuofia, which fails to yield a true synthesis. Universal belonging would naturally produce an equitable result in the land case because all parties would associate with a single identity. Self-interest would motivate fairness without external coercion. 

Cosmopolitan ethics is not without its own difficulties, however. Unfavorable representations of the unity of humanity suggest a disinclination on the part of colonizers to adopt a universal identity. Chinua Achebe observes in “An Image of Africa: Racism in Conrad’s Heart of Darkness” that the possibility of commonalty with the Africans is disconcerting for their colonizers: “It is not the differentness that worries Conrad but the lurking hint of kinship, of common ancestry” (2). A shared history is a vital part of a universal history, and the histories of Africa and Europe are substantially intertwined. Yet Achebe argues that Africa is often used as a foil for Europe, so as to support the idea of civilization. Privileging European difference by devaluating African “negation” threatens global identity, a concept of universal civilization that incorporates Afrocentric and Eurocentric value-systems harmoniously. In Rudyard Kipling’s The Man Who Would Be King, a similar assessment of common identity is used to justify mass exploitation. Daniel assumes a commonalty between Englishmen and the people of Kafiristan: “They're the Lost Tribes, or something like it, and they've grown to be English” (2.42). He is not interested in cultivating the relationship between the traditions of England and Kafiristan to achieve a unified identity; instead, he intends to exploit the human capital of Kafiristan. The interest of colonizers in manipulating the idea of a shared identity to their advantage also threatens the nature of traditions unique to certain cultures. Cultural authenticity is often subordinated to what colonizing societies perceive as social progress. 

Global identity cannot accommodate relationships of privilege between cultural values; however, colonizers often manipulate values of the colonized in the name of progress. A principal method they use to do so is education or technical training. In Heart of Darkness, an African has been trained to operate the boiler of a ship. Marlow, who describes the man as an “improved specimen” (98),  elaborates on the training that was given: “[The African] was useful because he had been instructed; and what he knew was this--that should the water in that transparent thing disappear, the evil spirit inside the boiler would get angry through the greatness of his thirst, and take a terrible vengeance” (99). The “improvement” that training brings to the African culture is a privileging of technical knowledge over the aesthetic. In George Orwell’s “Shooting an Elephant,” the elephant is technology for the colonized and an aesthetic object for the colonizer. This difference in perception is an indicator of underlying relationships of difference, supported by political power-relations. Similarly, Marlow depicts the religious beliefs of the African, an essential cultural value, as aesthetic opinions that have been manipulated for the technological purposes of the colonizer. The colonizer privileges the utility of the technological use of religion above its culturally authentic aesthetics. A problem arises for cosmopolitan ethics when the utility of cultural manipulation is justified on the basis of social progress. Educated Africans can contribute to the progress of civilization, while the uneducated cannot, the assumption goes. Colonizers further argue that only colonizing countries can advance civilization. Addressing the supposed benevolence of the idea of progress reveals important normative political views associated with global identity. 

The universal belongingness of cosmopolitan ethics includes a conception of social progress that does not rely on privileging the cultural values of the colonizer above those of the colonized. Cosmopolitan justice defies the colonial model of advancement through imperial expansion. A sense of domesticity is extended to all countries, which creates self-identification apart from ownership. Global identification enables one to feel at home anywhere on Earth, not merely in one’s country of origin. Derek Walcott’s “A Far Cry From Africa” illustrates the tension that privileging cultural values causes: “The gorilla wrestles with the superman” (25). The struggle in which the two countries engage causes the speaker to confront a difficult choice: “how choose / Between this Africa and the English tongue I love?” (29-30) Cosmopolitan ethics eliminates the need to choose between cultures, as difference no longer divides cultural identities. The consequence is a universal sense of domesticity. Affairs of one country have universal importance, as Walcott concludes: “How can I turn from Africa and live?” (33)  The life of the individual is intimately associated with the status of every country, and associating with other countries cannot sever the relationship. There is no difficult choice or struggle. Progress as defined by cosmopolitanism consists in the globalization of concerns that would otherwise be isolated to their country of origin. The ubiquity of cultural concerns also benefits the identities of individuals because it promotes greater continuity between colonizing and colonized countries. 

Place-oriented identity fragments when individuals travel between colonizing and colonized countries, partially because of encounters with abusive power-relations. Jasmine associates the emergence of an ideal Self with disassociation from a place-oriented, colonized identity: “We murder who we were so that we can rebirth ourselves in the images of dreams” (Mukherjee 29). Lucy expresses a similar transformation: “I had been a girl of whom certain things were expected, none of them too bad: a career as a nurse, for example; a sense of duty to my parents; obedience to the law and worship of convention. But in one year of being away from home, that girl had gone out of existence” (Kincaid 133). Both women react to abusive power-relations by altering their identities. Cosmopolitan ethics insists on the integrity of personal identity, which provides greater stability than place-oriented identity. Freedom apart from identification with the polis becomes possible when values of colonized countries become equally valued with those of colonizing countries. This yields post-national equality, which advances the project of global selfhood. The integrity of individual identity is largely connected to global identity, which the fourth-wave of postcolonial movement evidences. A return to formerly colonized countries requires a stable method of self-identification. Postcolonial studies recognizes the difficulty of cultural re-integration; a universal system of cultural values would solve this problem effectively as the world-polis emerges. 

I have been fascinated with problems of postcolonial identity throughout the course. Working with the Self-Other model of dialectical synthesis proved interesting but not as productive as I had hoped. Global identity offers a viable method of reconciling cultural differences without involving the troublesome concept of synthesis. While cosmopolitan ethics has yet to gain the philosophical credibility that Platonic political theories enjoy, its potential to support the emergence of fourth-wave postcolonial migration cannot be overlooked. The objection made to cosmopolitan ethics regarding social progress can be answered by observing the distinction between identification and ownership. A more satisfying and theoretically coherent political system emerges from the adoption of global identity. Cosmopolitan social progress and the idea of universal belongingness have the potential for philosophical expansion and would greatly benefit postcolonial studies if adopted. 

 

Gregory Buchanan 

11 December 2013

Reconstituting Self Through Internal Synthesis

In the model of cultural synthesis we have studied throughout the semester, difference stands between the identities of Self and Other. Usually difference expresses an attribute of the identity to which it belongs, and these attributes must be reconciled with those of an opposing identity if a synthesis is to be achieved. An assumption of the model is that difference is always external to the identities involved. It occurs in the mediating space between Self and Other, ideally where the two identities can be made to reach a point of mutually profitable compromise. However, synthesis within an identity also seems possible through the internalization of difference. The presence of an Other is not always necessary for a Self to encounter an attribute foreign to itself. Exploring the possibility of internal synthesis may explain the re-constitution of Self that several course texts illustrate. Intertextual descriptions of the stages Selves undergo in response to foreign attributes will unify the process in a continuous narrative that may also yield insight into the fourth-wave movement of postcolonialism. An intertextual reading of Jasmine, Passage to India, “The Second Coming,” and Things Fall Apart reveals the capacity of the Self to internally synthesize or reconstruct itself in response to foreign attributes of cultural Others. 

Jasmine’s explanation of the identity of Self suggests an initial stage of complete individuation prior to internal synthesis. When consulted about the nature of the Self, Jasmine describes its constitution in terms of several self-contained micro-identities that connect indeterminately: “What if the human soul is eternal--the swamis say of it, fires cannot burn it, water cannot drown it, winds cannot bend it--what if it is like a giant long-playing record with millions of tracks, each of them a complete circle with only one diamond-sharp microscopic link to the next life, and the next, and only God to hear it all?” (Mukherjee 127) She regards each “track” as its own entity that cannot be influenced by the one before or after. This conception seems problematic, as several texts suggest the reality of character development. More puzzling is the pairing of identities Jasmine also describes, especially since the correspondences are in terms of male-female relations. “I have had a husband for each of the women I have been. Prakash for Jasmine, Taylor for Jase, Bud for Jane. Half-Face for Kali” (Mukherjee 197). Each female identity is presented as having a male counterpart, so gender-relative identity may indicate relationships of Self and Other, yet no explanation is given regarding continuity in the partnerships. How the transition from one relationship to the next affects Jasmine’s identity is unclear at this point, but Jasmine seems to answer the question by positing that identity can respond to spontaneous changes in circumstance. 

Jasmine intimates the potential for identity to evolve when presented with favorable or unfavorable alterations in environment. Any response to foreign attributes at this stage is inadvertent. “And I do believe that extraordinary events can jar the needle arm, jump tracks, rip across incarnations, and deposit a life into a groove that was not prepared to receive it”  (Mukherjee 127). Assuming that there is substantial continuity between micro-identities, the difference between one and the next may not be significant, yet the reaction does prove a self-initiated connection to the external environment not dependent on the presence of an Other. Jasmine gives an example of an identity that abruptly ends upon the death of its partner: “When Jyoti’s future was blocked after the death of Prakash, Lord Yama should have taken her” (Mukherjee 127). Although it is unclear whether Jyoti dies in sense that Jasmine believes micro-identities can die, the emergence of another micro-identity definitely occurs. The absence of the Other corresponding to Jyoti seems to warrant the complete termination of Jyoti herself. Whether the Self is dependent on the Other for its continuity remains unanswered, but the absence of the Other seems to qualify as a foreign attribute for the Self. Absence may be the attribute most diametrically opposed to the Self, actually. 

The speaker of Passage to India examines whether Self may deliberately internalize difference to initiate the modification of its identity. Using the literal passage to India to signify the spiritual condition of Self, the speaker observes an internally-produced longing for exploration:  “Ah who shall soothe these feverish children? / Who Justify these restless explorations?” (5. 14-15) The desire for exploration seems self-initiated in response to the possibility of travel. Metaphorically, travel may suggest progress from spiritual mediocrity to spiritual excellence, or personal enhancement in some other sense. The possibility for travel is not a completely present Other and neither is India. An identity must be known for it to exist phenomenologically, and it must be positive, so the unknown India does not qualify as a completely present Other. Only in response to a partially-present other does the Self reconcile a foreign attribute, unrealized spiritual advancement, with its present condition. To emphasize the self-generated desire for exploration, the speaker identifies the explorer as in possession of himself or herself: “O soul, repressless, I with thee and thou with me, / Thy circumnavigation of the world begin, / Of man, the voyage of his mind’s return, / To reason’s early paradise,” (Whitman 7. 5-8). The explorer possesses his or her soul, or Self, and progress toward the undiscovered Other. At this stage, the process of internal synthesis seems to end with self-initiated recognition of a possible Other. 

The Self continues toward internal synthesis by desiring interaction with the Other, which it now recognizes through an incremental approach. The speaker establishes a relationship between the present and the past, which the Self is able to internally recognize: “For what is the present after all but a growth out of the past? / (As a projectile form’d, impell’d, passing a certain line, still keeps on, / So the present, utterly form’d, impell’d by the past.)” (Whitman 1. 13-15) This objective relationship of the passage of time, or experience in general,  causes the Self to anticipate future growth upon meeting the Other. Aspiring to self-improvement suggests recognition of present imperfection. The speaker expresses this recognition as the Self acknowledging the more perfect condition of an Other: “Athwart the shapeless vastnesses of space, / How should I think, how breathe a single breath, how speak if, out / of myself, / I could not launch, to those, superior universes?” (Whitman 8. 29-32) The “superiority” of unknown universes is the foreign attribute to which the Self initiates its internal change. Ideally the Self aspires to radical and not marginal improvement, which the speaker indicates by naming physical entities that harbor significant spiritual meaning: “O sun and moon and all you stars! Sirius and Jupiter! / Passage to you!” (Whitman 9. 17-18) Having acknowledged the Other and fully formed a desire for its presence, the Self completes the final stage of internal synthesis and admits that attributes that reflect the nature of the Other can be internalized to signify aspects of the Self. 

In response to an almost completely present Other, the Self originates comparisons between its attributes and those of the Other prior to their synthesis. In William Yeats’s “The Second Coming,” the nature of dialectical synthesis is perceived in the re-iterative manifestations of history. The title alludes to the return of Christ, whose incarnation is not supposed to materially change, only appear again on the Earth. In the same sense, the Self can internally recognize the possibility of expressing its attributes in a new identity--the identity it will produce upon its synthesis with the Other. Because the synthesis between Self and Other is not an exact replication of either identity, the description of history offered by the speaker can also be applied to dialectical synthesis: “Turning and turning in the widening gyre” (1). Both Self and Other are reflected in the identity of the synthesis; all syntheses may create the figure of a non-repeating gyre if combined. The speaker illustrates the non-repeating natures of history and dialectical synthesis with two images. “Things fall apart; the centre cannot hold; (3). This image seems related to course objective six, which discusses the tendency of traditional societies to attribute significance to place, while modern societies view place in terms of undifferentiated space. The second image reveals a “new” center: “A shape with lion body and the head of a man,” (14). Because the Sphinx combined two consecutive symbols of the zodiac, Virgo and Leo, it was understood by ancient Egyptians to mark the center of the universe. Because the Self has not yet synthesized with the Other, its preparation is internal and consists of recognizing the nature of the synthesis of difference. The internal synthesis of Self ends with its recognition of the pattern of dialectical synthesis; a fully present Other becomes evident to the Self subsequently. 

Internal synthesis can be understood in terms of masculine and feminine identities, as a re-constituted Self interacts with foreign attributes without fully encountering an Other. Self re-constitution appears concretely in Chinua Achebe’s Things Fall Apart. When Okonkwo lives in his fatherland, Umuofia, he belongs to one aspect of his parentage and not to the other. “A man belongs to his fatherland and not to his motherland” (Achebe 133). Okonkwo does not recognize the absence of the Other, which is his motherland, Mbanta, but he acknowledges the existence of several other villages. Presumably he is aware of his motherland prior to his exile. Influences from villages within Umuofia constitute the foreign attributes which Okonkwo reconciles within himself. A member of the tribal judiciary, Okonkwo works closely with representatives of all of the nine subsidiary villages of Umuofia to produce decisions based on their various customs. These sources of cultural difference permit Okonkwo to re-constitute himself through internalized difference. Okonkwo comments on the customs of other villages, especially relating to marriage, and observes their differences. When Okonkwo is exiled from Umuofia and must live in Mbanta, he encounters the cultural Other with which his identity is synthesized. 

Okonkwo is more amenable to synthesis with his motherland because of the internal re-constitution he underwent in his fatherland. Although the exile is painful for Okonkwo, he can withstand it because of his hope to return to Umuofia. When he appears to suffer impatiently among the kinsmen of his mother, Uchendu explains that the motherland is central to his identity: “It’s true that a child belongs to its father. But when a father beats his child, it seeks sympathy in its mother’s hut. A man belongs to his fatherland when things are good and life is sweet. But when there is sorrow and bitterness he finds refuge in his motherland (Achebe 134). Having lived in both the fatherland and the motherland, Okonkwo’s return to Umuofia is not an experience with a genuine Other. Although Umuofia changed in his absence, and he lost his place of honor in the tribal judiciary, Okonkwo finds that many traditions are the same. Masculine and feminine influences on his identity have blended to produce a cooperative Self that facilitates his re-integration into Umuofia. Although Okonkwo does not regain his position of trial leadership--and is denied further reconstitution while in the fatherland--he realizes considerable benefit from the Self-orientation already in his possession. Like Okonkwo, many possessors of postcolonial identity are in ideal positions to re-integrate into societies that are experiencing substantial economic development. 

The fourth-wave of postcolonialism consists of movement toward previously colonized countries, such as India. While its potential has not yet been fully realized, trends of economic development are expected to continue in its favor. People who have identities influenced by the cultures of these countries, either through full synthesis or re-constitution, have a definite advantage if they choose to immigrate. In “A Passage From India,” Suketu Mehta explains: “Indian-Americans will help America understand India, trade with it to our mutual benefit. Just as Arab-Americans can help us fight Al Qaeda, Indian-Americans can help us deal with the emerging economic superpower that is India. This is the return of the gift of citizenship” (3). Through re-constitution of Self, Americans can take advantage of the growing forth-wave economic trends; this would involve remaining in the United States and exposing oneself to the foreign attributes of Indian culture. A more extreme version of preparation is complete synthesis: one would re-locate to India and synthesize one’s identity completely. Masculine and feminine influences on identity could also be explained in terms of secondary nationalities, but many Americans do not maintain dual-citizenship or participate in the cultures of radically different nations. 

Self has the capacity to re-constitute itself through internal synthesis. The presence of an Other is not necessary for internal synthesis, as attributes of foreign identity can be internalized by the Self autonomously. Masculine and feminine attributes of identity can express the nature of postcolonial identity achieved through re-constitution, especially as it relates to the fourth-wave of postcolonialism. Course objective 2a asks how colonial and postcolonial fiction may help people better understand our global future. Understanding identity-relations in an economically global world can be difficult, but postcolonial fiction often features characters who are removed from their homelands and subsequently re-introduced. Similarly, characters frequently adapt to new cultures, which could encourage Americans to embrace economic trends that may encourage immigration to another country. Political science relations between countries on the basis of immigration also appear peripherally in postcolonial fiction.