Stephen Defferari
23
November 2016
Reader-Response, Phenomenology, and the ‘Uncanny’ in Nathaniel
Hawthorne’s “Young Goodman Brown”
Even
though there are phenomena that readers would identify as ‘uncanny’ in
Hawthorne’s “Young Goodman Brown” and “The Minister’s Black Veil,” the term does
not appear in either story, and perhaps for good reason. Freud “recognized that
people vary greatly in their sensitivity to that [uncanny] quality of feeling,”
in which case it is not surprising if one does not experience the feeling at
all, whether the experience is supposed to derive from phenomena in reality or
texts (Newlin 84). Though what is interesting about his assertion that
literature posses “more means of creating uncanny effects than there are in real
life,” it creates a subsequent need to resolve the difference between “effect”
and “feeling” (Freud 950). The ability or inability of a text to inculcate in
readers an ‘uncanny’ feeling foregrounds two concerns which are equally relevant
to the subject of readership and hermeneutics: the critical approach to the
text, and the “personal assumptions and interpretive protocols” of readers
(Leitch 1671).
Whether these aforementioned stories produce ‘uncanny’ feelings for readers or
not, the ability of readers to identify ‘uncanny’ effects in the text means that
they have must foreknowledge of the term which allows them to do so. I, for
example, did not experience any kind of feeling that I would describe as
‘uncanny’ when I read through these stories; however I do own a copy of
The Norton Anthology of Theory and
Criticism, and contained within this voluminous anthology is Sigmund Freud’s
book, The Uncanny, which allowed me
to identify ‘uncanny’ effects in these stories when I corroborated them with
definitions in Freud’s work. I am of the latter sort of readers whose critical
approach is conditioned by texts that have been scrutinized and published by
“interpretive communities,” and I do not typically approach a text to engage it
in a kind “co-creative” process (Fish 2085). Andrew Miller posits one reason or
this: “The methods and the object of cultural studies are mismatched,” since the
“symbolic “complex whole”” is contained within a cultural complex which is
“inaccessible to empirical observation” (Miller 165). Though not to deviate
needlessly from the problem, what is the difference between “feeling” and
“effects” in their relation to the ‘uncanny’?
I ask
the question outright because Hawthorne is prone to asking questions, questions
that cause me to question the presence and purpose of those questions in his
stories. But it seems a question is as much a matter of presence as it is
purpose, at least in “Young Goodman Brown.” The narrator questions the contents
of the basin during the unwholesome gathering – “Did is contain water, reddened
by the lurid light? or was it blood? Or, perchance, a liquid flame?” – and the
authenticity of the events – “Had Goodman Brown fallen asleep in the forest, and
only dreamed a wild dream of a witch-meeting?” (33-4). These are not the
interrogative thoughts of Goodman himself questioning his reality, since all of
his own questions (only two in number) occur in dialogue – “Can this be so?” –
or in thought – “But where is Faith?” (26, 32). The questions of the narrator,
if they are to be answered or not, are presumably directed towards an “implied
reader” (Iser 1671). By asking readers these questions the narrator indicates
that it is limited in its omniscience, and so depends partly upon the reader to
provide conjectures about the veracity of the events in the text.
All
that readers can do is apply judgement, not certainty.
The pivotal moment in
Stanley Fish’s essay, “Interpreting the
Variorium,” is when he asserts that readers “come away from…[poems] not with
a statement but with a responsibility, the responsibility of deciding” or
judging a problem or crux of a text (2074). Similarly, the presence of questions
in “Young Goodman Brown” gives to readers the responsibility of deciding the
answers to these questions. Maybe the questions are not meant to be answered.
Does it matter if the liquid in the basin is blood or water illuminated by red
light? Does it matter if the events are a dream of Goodman Brown or real in the
context? Readers have no way of knowing, so it is difficult to judge either way.
Judgement in general has a special place in the story because it is the “figure
of a man” who states that he has “drunk the communion wine...[with] a majority
of the Great and General Court” (Hawthorne 26). In all probability the answers
do not matter a great deal when compared with the effect of the events on the
subsequent perception of Brown. Though a basic understanding of baptism and
Puritan values will help to explain the import of these “effects” on his
perception.
For
Puritans, baptism is complicated by their theological program. To baptize
infants is problematic because infants have no knowledge of the Christian
denomination they are being born into, and subsequently have no knowledge of its
views on faith. Baptism without faith is to no avail for Puritans, nor can it
appropriate, call upon, or influence god’s salvific agency. In relation to the
story, the unholy baptismal in which Brown participates inducts him into a
community of “partakers of the mystery of sin, more conscious of the secret
guilt of others, both in deed and thought, than…of their own” (Hawthorne 33).
And in this capacity, “By the sympathy of [their] human hearts for sin [they
will] scent out all places – whether in church, bedchamber, street, field, or
forest – where crime has been committed, and shall exult to behold the whole
earth one stain of guilt, one mighty blood-spot” (33). The need of religious
context and additional texts in order to determine the “author’s horizon”
undermines the efficacy of a phenomenological mode of criticism, since
additional texts are required to determine the meaning of the “conscious
objects” of the author’s though process (Leitch 1683). Phenomenological theory,
however, is still relevant for the story when it is localized in Puritan
theology. If “Language brings man and his world into conscious existence,” and
“’Being’ is the realm of encounters…[between] subjects and objects…[which makes]
the spontaneous availability of each to the other,” then it is possible to
conceive of ‘faith’ and the ‘uncanny’ as peculiar instances of being (Leitch
1120; Eagleton 291).
The difference between the ‘uncanny’ and an instance of “supernatural
intelligence” is equal to the difference between “imaginative and supernatural
realities,” which is to say it is possible to trace the cause of one back to the
imagination while the other has no plausible relation to the imagination (Tatar
168). For English writer Dr. Samuel Johnson, an event of the ‘uncanny’ in some
way amounts to an “externalization of one’s consciousness” (Tatar 167). It is
“Knowledge…[that] serves as the key to Dr. Johnson’s ability to discriminate
between imaginary and supernatural reality,” insofar as the “passing on [of]
knowledge of alien matters” provides the only condition under which it is
possible to make the distinction between these two realities (Tatar 168). But
what if this “knowledge…is of something familiar and well known but forgotten,
repressed, or suppressed” in the mind of the person deliberating over the nature
of this knowledge and event (Tatar 168)? Or, in the example of Goodman Brown,
what if knowledge of those present at
the unholy communion – the minister, Old Deacon Gookin, Goody Cloyse, Faith, and
himself – occurs within a context that cannot be differentiated between the
dream world and reality? In Heideggerian terms, if “We speak when we are awake
and we speak in our dreams,” and language is the medium through which we are
engage in being, then being occurs regardless of the situation (1121).
The
problem, however, is with the word ‘faith’. Puritan theology does not allow the
physical to influence the spiritual, which is to say “Spiritual grace has no
connection whatsoever with corporeal or physical realities” (Spronk). But this
opens-up a spirit-body dualism which seems to be irreconcilable. If one is not
able to influence the spirit or the spiritual agency of god in a physical
medium, then how can one’s body affect one’s spirit? ‘Faith’ is a word without a
material object present in reality (except of course Goodman’s wife). It is not
an ‘object’ that is available in reality to bring consciousness and the world
into simultaneous existence. The assigning of names is equivalent to the
“tearing [of] objects away from the temporality which is of their essence”
(Eagleton 288). The word ‘faith’ is assigned to a spiritual essence or
internally kept being which has no foreseeable materiality. In many ways it is
for Puritans a timeless state of being without reference to the being or
sinfulness of the body and its relationship to the body has always been a topic
of debate. ‘Spirit’ in Christianity is always synonymous with inclusiveness and
collectivism, for all Christians attest to having a ‘spirit’ which can nether be
differentiated from the ‘spirit’ of others, nor can it be thought of as separate
from the substance of god. In Kantian terms, “any particular act of cognition”
represents how “mind and world shape up to each other in some unspoken compact,”
but even still this “mind” retains an uncertain relationship to ‘spirit’
(Eagleton 291).
If ‘being’ and “the world are…correlatives of one another,” and ‘faith’ is a
term given to an ideal object not perceptible in the world, then it can be
thought of as a particular type of being in a world created by Puritan theology.
This religious conditioning of the world creates an ontological conflict,
insofar as ‘Being’ becomes mediated by conditions created in a social context
that depends upon restrictions, separations, and regulations – in effect,
conditions which reinforce one’s separateness from objects in the world. ‘Being
for Heidegger is modified by “an actual social environment,” which is to say
this environment creates circumstances of separation that cause ‘Being’ to
become “covered up and forgotten” (Eagleton 294). To name Brown’s wife
‘Faith’ is to symbolically embody an
abstract term which represents immateriality, and then to have Brown temporarily
leave Faith “evil purpose” is the same as to have him abandon the Puritan world
altogether (Hawthorne 25). The inconsistency is the juxtaposition between
materiality and immateriality which occurs in the figure of Faith.
Metaphorically, to leave the Puritan understanding of faith at the “threshold”
is equal to abandoning a mode of being which is inconsistent with the material
needs and necessities of reality. However, the inconsistency occurs because
Faith is also the name of his wife, a corporeal figure assigned the name Faith.
The issue of the perception of the body is at stake in Brown’s leaving: either
he is abandoning Faith and a mode of being which disparages the materiality of
the world, or he is abandoning corporality and also the materiality which is
sustained and predicated by procreation and marriage. I cite the word
“threshold” in the story because it represents Heidegger’s “dif-ference,” in
which “the gathering of things and world in stillness happens” (Leitch 1120).
Therefore, his crossing of this “threshold” is the severance of his ‘Being’ from
Faith, and from all the socioreligious connotations which it represents. As
Eagleton states, “ in a crisis of resolution” similar to that of Brown when he
crosses the “threshold”), ‘Being’ “chooses to be what it is, recognizes its
possibilities as its own rather than as determined by the anonymous Other, and
projects itself forward towards death in a movement of separation from and
re-engagement with the objects of its concern” (295). And further: “Such
movements could be seen as a kind of rupturing of its ‘imaginary’ relations with
the world – an entry into the ‘symbolic order’ whose structures are those of
finitude, difference, individuation and death” (295). Though of course this all
depends on the state of the events in the text – was it a dream or was it real?
– and what this state means for the ‘Being’ of Goodman Brown. Three things
subsequently need to be resolved: determining if the events in the story are
‘uncanny’; the relationship the ‘uncanny’ to the real or dream state of Brown;
and the “effect” of these potentially uncanny event upon Brown’s ‘Being’.
One of Freud’s definitions of the ‘uncanny’ refers to that which arouses
sensations of “dread and horror” or fright, and “leads back to what is known of
old and long familiar” (Freud 930). Brown experiences doubt about his
willingness to continue down the “dreary road” to the unholy communion, though
it is not until he thinks that his “Faith is gone!” (Hawthorne 30). At this
moment he experiences “grief, rage, and terror,” so much so that his emotional
state become a strange amalgam of madness and despair (30). If “There is no good
on earth,” and “sin is but a name,” then this means that there can be no sin
because there is no “good” to contrast it with; though if this is so, then he
should not have subsequently evoked the “Devil,” since Satan is a fallen angel
who owes its existence to God – a contrastive force of “good” (30). Brown only
re-crosses the threshold that he crossed earlier in his abandonment of Faith
when he evokes Satan, seeing that both God and Satan are oppositional forces who
operate in the same theological world of being that is associated with ‘faith’.
‘Grace’ is effectively the opposite of ‘sin’, as ‘evil’ is the opposite of
‘good’, and ‘faith’ the opposite of ‘guilt’. Maintaining these oppositional
terms does not allow Brown to escape the totality of the theological system
which has defined his ‘Being’.
The
only way to do so would be to entirely deny Christianity and adopt another
religious or existential system of being. That “Evil is the nature of mankind”
also means that there is an oppositional term – good – to offset the imbalance
(33). What is ‘uncanny’ about the scene of the unholy communion is not the
participants, but the context. Tatar claims that “Uncanny events have the power
to provoke a sense of dread precisely because they are at once strange and
familiar” (169). The “evil” exoteric context of the communion is what makes the
familiarity of the participants from Salem ‘uncanny’, since the context is what
makes them unheimlich – or
‘unhomely’. The presence of associative terms,
heimlich and
unheimlich, indicates a “genesis
of…double meaning…on the nature of a house or home: A house contains the
familiar and the congenial, but at the same time it screens what is familiar and
congenial from view, making a mystery of it” (Tatar 169).
If one experiences an ‘uncanny’ series of events in reality or a dream, does it
change the overall uncanniness of its effect? The problem with being able to
determine whether or not the experience of Goodman Brown can be identified as
‘uncanny’ is the ambiguity of his emotional state following the loss of Faith in
the wood, and after the concluding of the experience. Following his experience,
the narrator states that Brown has become “A stern, a sad, a darkly meditative,
a distrustful, if not desperate man…from the night of that fearful dream”
(Hawthorne 34). Whether the dream is true or not is superfluous to the
disorienting effect it has wrought upon the life of Brown. He “turns pale”
during the minister’s sermon, and he abstains from the “bosom of Faith,”
presumably owing to the aftereffects of the experience (34). This effect seems
to correspond with notions associated with the ‘uncanny’ exactly for the reason
that it has altered his perceptions of his fellow citizens of Salem.
The
difference that has occurred is that is ‘Being’ has shifted from one of ‘faith’
to one of ‘guilt’, insofar as it represents his induction into the “loathful
brotherhood by the sympathy of all that was wicked in his heart” (Hawthorne 32).
The questions that the narrator directly asks readers work to involve them into
these ‘uncanny’ effects, and to question them. For the same reason that I do not
experience an ‘uncanny’ sensation upon reading the text, the effects thereof at
least incite readers to reevaluate the interpretive “protocols” that we use to
evaluate textual phenomena. Though what is truly sinful or guilt-creating about
the events of Goodman Brown? If Puritan dualism posits that we cannot influence
the spiritual agency of god (even though we supposedly posses a spirit), then
how is it that god has either the interest or intention to influence the
physical? If god was not working through the psyche of Goodman, whether he is
dreaming or not, then the events are simply products of Goodman’s imagination.
All of the hypotheticals which derive from the narrator’s questions not only
work to undermine any sort of ‘uncanny’ feeling which the text may produce, but
they specifically force readers to examine the effects of the events. Though
even with these effects, what are readers to make of Brown’s changed state?
It
seems ambiguous to have made him “conscious of the secret guilt of others,” both
in terms of “deed and thought” (Hawthorne 33). At worst, the act of abandoning
faith lead him to a communion of his
heimlich fellow citizens, in which they all become “partakers of the mystery
of sin” (33). If it is a dream sequence, then the ‘uncanny’ purpose of the dream
perhaps amounts to an “externalization of [his] consciousness,” in which his
abandonment of faith becomes a source of his guilt (Tatar 167). The problem is
with relation of the ‘canny’ and the ‘uncanny’ to ‘faith’ and ‘guilt
(respectively): a loss of ‘faith’ in that which is unfamiliar (i.e. the spirit
of immaterial) gives way to ‘guilt’, a familiarity with either a sense of wrong
or ‘sin associated with a series of actions or beliefs. ‘Faith’ cannot be known
because the spirit cannot be known, since Puritan theology asserts that the body
has no way of influencing the spirit. Subsequently, if ‘faith’ is the defining
mode of being in Heideggerian terms, then amounts to either an absence of
self-knowledge, or an absence of ‘Being’ in general. Ye the point of the unholy
communion that Goodman attends is to have knowledge of other people’s sin rather
than his own. I think that the point of this paradox is that ‘faith’ and ‘guilt’
are heterogeneous terms which complicate ‘Being’ in general. How can one possess
‘faith’, an unknown relation to an unknowable god, and ‘guilt’ simultaneously,
when Puritan theology adheres to the notion of ‘original sin’. If everyone is
inherently rendered ‘guilty’ by original sin, then the idea of ‘faith’ calls
into question human agency: if the willful act of having ‘faith’ is a function
of reason, then does reason have its source in the body, spirit, or some
composite of the two.
Works
Cited
Eagleton, Terry. “The Politics of Being: Martin Heidegger.”
The Ideology of the Aesthetic.
Blackwell, 1990, pp. 288-316.
Freud, Sigmund. “The Uncanny.” The Norton
Anthology of Theory and Criticism, edited by Vincent B. Leitch,
Norton and Co., 2001,
pp. 1622-1636.
Iser,
Wolfgang. “Interaction between Text and Reader.”
The Norton Anthology of Theory and
Criticism, edited by Vincent B. Leitch, Norton and Co., 2001, pp. 1670-1682.
Hirsch, E.D. “Objective Interpretation.”
The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism, edited by Vincent B. Leitch,
Norton and Co., 2001, pp. 1682-1709.
Fish,
Stanley. “Interpreting the Variorum.”
The Norton Anthology of Theory and
Criticism, edited by Vincent B.
Leitch, Norton and Co., 2001, pp. 2067-2071.
Miller, Andrew. “The Uncanny and Cynicism in Cultural History.”
Cultural Critique vol. 29, 1994, pp.
163-182.
Tatar, Maria. “Toward a definition of the Uncanny.”
Comparative Literature, vol. 33, no.
2, 1981, pp. 167-182.
|