| |
Jenny Brewer
20 Nov. 2011
Research Journal
Narrativity: Thirteen Concerns
Introduction:
I asked to do this research journal on narrativity after my midterm research led
me to an article titled “Narrativity and Knowledge,” by Paisley Livingston,
which explored “postulated connections between narrativity and the epistemic
merits or demerits of narratives” (Livingston, 25). Livingston had noticed a
growing number of divergent claims in literature dealing with narrative: either
scholars asserted that narratives generate epistemic irrationality, or that
certain types of knowledge could only be portrayed through narrative.
One camp seems to be claiming that narratives distort truth, and the
other hints that narratives reveal truth in ways that other representative forms
cannot. As our course objectives
concerning narrative were intriguing to me, narrativity seemed an ideal topic
for my project.
I have two personal experiences which make this topic appealing to me. The first
is actually more of a tendency- when faced with a dilemma in my day to day life,
too often my first efforts at determining a course of action involve trying to
think of a book or a movie where a character has faced the same situation, and
seeking guidance from their decisions. I have often found this disturbing in
myself, and have even toyed with the idea of creating a searchable website where
people can post their real-life
dilemmas, so that this same kind of “research” can be done in the context of
messy reality instead of the too-neat world of narrative. Fortunately, I am
saved from this undertaking by the existence of
The Experience Project: “the world's largest collection of life
experiences, personal stories, and the people who have had them”
(experienceproject.com).
The second experience motivating this research is a bit more serious: the
experience of having lived through the greatest advances in civil rights for
gays and lesbians in modern history. Credit for the progress we have made in the
last thirty years is largely due to the coming out movement, in that
discrimination decreases as visibility increases (D'Augelli, 126). This is
because people's lives are narratives, so hearing stories about GLBT lives has
been exponentially more effective than having homosexuality removed from the
DSM. An even stronger example of
this principle at work is the “It Gets Better” video project.
In this case, rather than using our stories to gain acceptance from those
who are ignorant of our reality, we have used our stories to save the lives of
those who know it all too well.
.
These two examples show how I already had experience
with both sides of the divergence being explored in “Narrative and Knowledge.”
My temptation to seek answers in fictional stories demonstrates to me some of
narrative's questionable powers, in that the made-up worlds I have been exposed
to take root in my head in a way that makes them seem more real than the
experiences of people I have actually met. On the other hand, the impact of the
coming out movement and of the “It Gets Better” project have been a force for
good in my day-to-day life.
Holding these two opposing perspectives
simultaneously meant that happening upon Paisley Livingston's examination of
narratives rang bells in my head. Ms.
Livingston lays out thirteen claims regarding narrative power: seven on the
“con” side and six on the “pro.” For my research project, I proposed a journal -
in which I would evaluate these claims for myself by finding examples of each
within the colonial and postcolonial literature that we've studies this
semester. My journal comprises thirteen entries, one for each of the claims in
Ms. Livingston's article. Within each entry I have attempted to identify
“classic” examples from mainstream culture, paired with examples from our class
readings. Where possible, I have sought out the sources cited in Ms.
Livingston's article and included thoughts from these, as well.
All of the articles I read began by discussing a definition of “narrative.” I
say “discussing a definition” rather than “defining” because there is some
uncertainty. For the purposes of this paper, I will use the definition included
in our class objectives, defining narrative as a “personal and cultural
trajectory, direction, or history.” I feel fortunate to have this definition
available, as none of my sources were able to agree. One scholar even referred
to narrative as “a black box;” something that “recieves inputs from the
determinants of narrativity and gives as outputs representations of certain
favored states of affairs,” (Currie, 311).
1.
The first argument Livingston identifies accusing
narrative of distortion
concerns the potential for narratives to be
“pseudo-explanatory: narratives embody or encourage the fallacy of
post hoc ergo propter hoc”
(Livingston, 25).
Post hoc ergo propter hoc
is Latin for "after this, therefore because of this." It is a logical fallacy in
that it assumes that effects following an event must be caused by an event. A
classic example of this occurs in romantic comedies when the geeky heroine finds
love after exchanging her glasses for contacts. Geeky girls all over the world
will now blame their glasses for their lack of dates, instead of understanding
that the liberation from self-stereotyping
represented by the change might have altered their
lives regardless of eyewear. A variation on this tendency can be observed in
Heart of Darkness, when
Marlow assumes that his hired cannibals did not eat him because they share his
English values of restraint (Conrad, 67). Marlow has a narrative in his head
concerning Englishness and its causes and effects, so when an incident
intersects with this narrative at a single point, he sees this intersection as
an explanation. This is a variation in that the cause follows from a
quality (the assumed
Englishness of the cannibals' restraint), rather than an event, but it is still
a good example in that it portrays a character attributing a false cause to an
event.
2.
The second argument Livingston identifies accusing narrative of distortion
concerns the potential for narratives to be “pseudo-justificatory: the
persuasive appeal of stories is disproportionate to their real evidential
support or reliability (narrative generates “cold” irrationality as a result of
availability, salience, and confirmation biases)” (Livingston, 25).
In popular culture this can be seen in stories that romanticize the
antebellum South, and thus minimize slavery's brutality.
Crusoe's relationship with Friday works in the same way- Europeans wanted
to believe that colonial natives needed a civilizing influence, and Defoe's
portrayal of Friday's gratitude confirmed this (Defoe, 295). Khushwant Singh,
discussing his first published short story, admits to intentionally playing on
confirmation biases: “it was kind of a hammy story, deliberately-- you know how
the foreigner expects India to have stories about things like snakes […] so
there was a snake in it” (Mahfil, 27).
Singh wanted to appeal to white Europeans, so he made sure that his work
would satisfy at least one of the expectations they brought to it.
3.
The third argument Livingston identifies accusing
narrative of distortion
concerns the potential for narratives to be
“misleading: stories encourage the error of
pars pro toto”
(Livingston,
25). Pars
pro toto
is the fallacy of taking a part for
the whole, and occurs when we assume that we fully understand a concept by
virtue of having been exposed to it.
This is most obvious in “A Small Place.”
Jamaica Kincaid speaks directly to those who would imagine they “know” the
Antilles because they have been to a beach there (Kincaid, 257). We see in
Jasmine how Bud
Ripplemeyer's preexisting understanding of the East,
“plunges me into visibility and wisdom,” allowing
him to believe he understands her despite an outright refusal to hear her story
(Mukherjee, 178). The Western cultural narrative of colonialism allows him to
believe he
knows her simply because he “knows” the myth.
4.
The fourth argument Livingston identifies accusing narrative of distortion
concerns the potential for narratives to be “seductive: a story’s narrativity is
likely to lead to “hot” irrationality through its strong or even “irresistible”
emotional appeal, which is obtained at the price of cognitive shortcomings”
(Livingston, 25). The War of the
Worlds is a classic example. James Bruner asserts that “great storytellers
have the artifices of narrative reality construction so well mastered that their
telling preempts momentarily the possibility of any but a single interpretation-
however bizarre it may be,” (Bruner, 9). Orson Welles so thoroughly manipulated
text, context, and setting that listeners nationwide believed instantly in
something that would have seemed ridiculous just one day before. We see the life
story of Sir James Brooke work in this way upon Dravot and Peachey in “The Man
Who Would be King.” They are so
seduced by the image of going from soldier to Rajah in one short military step
that they fail to consider the vast differences between their characters and
Brooke's, and in different circumstances of time and place (Kipling).
For example, involving themselves in local skirmishes did work to
their advantage, but not nearly so well as it might have if they had done so in
such a way as to inspire gratitude in someone equivalent to the Sultan of Brunei
(Cavendish, 55). The lack of such a personage severely limited how high their
fortunes could rise, but they were so impressed by the end of Sir Brooke's story
that they overlooked this way in which his differed from theirs.
5.
The fifth argument Livingston identifies accusing
narrative of distortion
concerns the potential for narratives to be “proleptic
or “prophetic”: narrators provide a
retrospective account of events, deceptively presented from an anticipatory
perspective” (Livingston, 26). In Things Fall Apart,
we see the British District Commissioner attempt to turn Okonkwo's death to this
purpose (Achebe, 209). He contemplates how to insert the incident into an
ethnography he is compiling as part of his plan to “turn the colonizing
enterprise into a message and to cast agents of its violent spread as motiveless
messengers,” (Adeeko, 39). Because Okonkwo dies by his own hand, the
Commissioner can cherry-pick the events leading up to his death in such a way as
to make suicide the inevitable result of rebellion. A classic example comes from
Aristotle, who notes that “even coincidences are most striking when they have an
air of design,” (Aristotle, 39). He is referring to the death of Mitys's
murderer, who was crushed by a statue of Mitys that fell on him during a
festival. The falling of the statue seems wholly random taken by itself, but
seems fated when presented retrospectively.
6.
The sixth argument Livingston identifies accusing narrative of distortion
concerns the potential for narratives to be “empirically unsound by virtue of
selectivity or closure,” (Livingston, 26). The example of Mitys's murderer gives
us a clue as to why this is. The murder of Mitys and the death of his killer are
not actually related in any way.
However, the two events combined make a good story, despite Aristotle's stated
rule that an event in a plot “should be the necessary or probable result of the
preceding action” (Aristotle, 41).
It appears that an exception to this rule exists for events that provide an
emotional resolution (Velleman, 6).
Finding emotional resolution for a murder through a completely unrelated
accident definitely qualifies as “empirically unsound.”
The quality of being empirically unsound through selectivity is probably
why I tend to turn to novels and movies in my own problem-solving: a story is
only worth telling if it is out of the ordinary (Bruner, 12). Therefore, when I
am wracking my brain for examples of the situation before me, I am naturally
going to find more examples in narratives – because every narrative I am exposed
to features an unusual situation, and the flesh-and-blood people I know only
have unusual things happen to them occasionally.
The aforementioned example of the British District Commissioner's literary
aspirations illustrates this contention as well: the closure provided by
Okonkwo's hanging is what makes the incident so attractive – such an ending
would appear to the outsider to constitute a ready-made cautionary tale against
resistance (Achebe, 209). From the Commissioner's viewpoint, it is a perfect
fable with an instructive moral, but from the perspective of one of Okonkwo's
wives or children it is completely different. This is because Okonkwo's wife and
children are outside of the neat circle of closure that limns the story for the
commissioner. This contradiction
scales easily from the microcosm of Things Fall Apart all the way up to
the macrocosm of all narratives everywhere. In fact, this is the issue which has
split the study of narratology into structuralist and contextualist approaches -
with structuralists tending to study individual narratives from within the
context defined by the narrative, and contextualists asking whether narratology
shouldn't “consider the acts in the real world that generate literary narratives
[as being] more significant than the resultant products,” (Chatman, 310).
Our cross-textual studies in Colonial and Postcolonial narratives provide
and excellent antidote to this, as our course has been structured in such a way
as to “nest” each text inside an opposing text – meaning that whatever false
closure a Colonial text sets up will be immediately exploded the following week.
It is also important to note that, besides considering the context of the
narrative's creation, a narrative's meaning is also affected by the context of
its transmission and by the context of its reception.
Bruner reminds us that “narrative is a conventional form, transmitted
culturally and constrained by each individual's level of mastery and by his
conglomerate of prosthetic devices, colleagues, and mentors,” (4). On an
unrelated note – Bruner also (amusingly) categorizes “excuses” as narratives.
Besides the issue of the context within which a narrative is created, there is
also the issue of realities that narratives create. Bruner speculates that
evolution in narrative techniques - “the advent of 'inner adventure' in Tristram
Shandy, the advent of Flaubert's perspectivism, or Joyce's epiphanizing of
banalities” - have shaped the way we interpret events happening to us in our
day-to-day lives (12).
7.
The seventh argument Livingston identifies accusing narrative of distortion
concerns the potential for narratives to be “empirically misleading by virtue of
an overemphasis on agency, or on agents’ responsibility or freedom,”
(Livingston, 26). An extreme example of this is the traditional use of
Robinson Crusoe to justify Free Trade economic theory, which states that
before Crusoe meets Friday, his consumption is constrained by his own production
possibility curve, but after they meet they are able to specialize producing
those goods in which they each have a comparative advantage (Samson ,143). This
usage vastly overemphasizes agency, in that Crusoe had absolutely no choice in
his isolation or in his partnership with Friday, making it outrageously
misleading to imply that what was the only course of action for a fictional
character could be the best course of action for economies. In fact,
overemphasis on agency comes up in every armchair economist debate I allow
myself to get sucked into: the “bootstrap myth” is ubiquitous among my relatives
- even the ones on public assistance.
8.
The first argument Livingston identifies that supports the power of narrative is
“the potential for narratives to be sound because of a correspondence with
patterns of lived experience (such as temporality) or by virtue of descriptions
of particular cases that are instructive counterexamples to bad theories or
analytic generalizations,” (Livingston, 26). Evidence indicates that narrative
comprehension is one of the earliest faculties to develop in children, and that
narrative is one of the most common ways humans organize their experiences
(Bruner, 9). Bruner posits an alternative to narrative seduction in “narrative
banality,” which operates in precisely this manner: taking a narrative as “so
socially conventional, so well known, so in keeping with the canon, that we can
assign it to some well-rehearsed and virtually automatic interpretive routine,”
(9). We can reveal correspondences between narrative and lived experience quite
easily, simply by comparing the human life cycle to Freytag's Pyramid. Such
comparison instantly reveals correspondences between youth and “exposition” and
“rising action,” between adulthood and “complication” and “reversal”,” and
between old age an “falling action” (Wheeler). This means that we have a
tendency to automatically identify with any narrator, just because their story
reminds us of our own in that both stories have a beginning, middle, and end.
This automatic identification means that we can be more easily forced
into seeing things the narrator's way, even when the narrator's perspective is
in opposition to our own. We can
then experience the metaphorical equivalent of “walking a mile in another's
shoes,” and might be prompted to discard old prejudices. Feminist critics posit
this as Lucy's entire program, noting that “Lucy controls the
dissemination of knowledge to the reader so that her point of view is always
visible first and helps to shape the reader's perspective,” and that “this
narrative privileging allows Lucy to sift through Western binary power
discourses,” (Nichols, 189).
9.
The second argument Livingston identifies supporting narrative is that narrative
is “a basic mode of thought and way of ordering experience that is efficient,
modular, memorable, and engaging” (Livingston 26).
As my classmate, Keaton Patterson, states in his midterm essay, Robinson
Crusoe takes advantage of this to shape the culture of imperialism in which it
was produced. Crusoe's development of a parent-child dynamic between himself and
Friday models the relationship between England and her colonial possessions. It
is interesting that “even after decades of solitude, Crusoe is excited at the
prospects of acquiring a servant rather than a relationship with an equal,”
(Keaton). England echoes this behavior in the manner in which they never seem to
consider asking their colonial subjects to simply sell them their rubber or oil,
but rather proceed to extract it for themselves and abscond with it as if there
were no question of ownership. As my classmate Jessica Peterson points out, this
posture is obvious even in Crusoe's naming of Friday, in that Crusoe feels
supremely comfortable choosing a name from within his own only-hours-old
acquaintance with him, instead of attempting to choose a name that has any
relation to Friday as a person. The Crusoe narrative's inherent power is
amplified immeasurably by virtue of the book's status as “the first modern
English novel.” Its powers worked all the more effectively because readers had
not yet learned of narrative's potential.
10.
The third argument Livingston identifies supporting narrative is that narrative
is “antidogmatic by virtue of 'context sensitivity and negotiability'”
(Livingston, 26). Lucy very aggressively exploits the antidogmatic
valence of literature by using the Lucy's vehement self-identification as an
“outsider” to openly critique “the cosmopolitan American Left of the 1960's,”
(Nichols, 187). “Kincaid is a spy in the house of American liberalism […] the
reader benefits from her critique by seeing things through a narrative that
shifts the dominant perspective out of the limelight,” (Nichols, 205).
This is especially obvious in Mariah's desire to confide in Lucy that she
“has Indian blood”(Kincaid, 39). Mariah's middle-class leftist outlook leads her
to believe that “having Indian blood” (never mind that it's only a drop, at the
most, and nothing in any way similar to Carib Indian blood) gives her a special
insight into Lucy's experience, and makes them “the same.” She offers up this
declaration like a gift to Lucy – her most precious possession - with no concept
of how erasing this is to one who has lived as an Indian. The idea of erasing
racial differences by focusing on commonalities with
the oppressed is a classic fallacy of well-meaning whites, who seem to
feel that by “rejecting” their privilege they are leveling the playing field –
when, in fact, one cannot “erase” racial differences without erasing the
experiences of those who have suffered racial oppression.
Lucy is antidogmatic in that Kincaid paints a very thorough
picture of Mariah's ideas of herself as a liberal, only to smash it to pieces
with this utterance that virtually all of the character's white liberal cohorts
would have championed. Then, to make absolutely sure we get the full impact,
Kincaid has Lucy explain further: this is the reason she's “so good at catching
fish and hunting birds and roasting corn,” spewing stereotypes right and left as
“proof” that she is more like Lucy than not (Kincaid, 39). This antidogmatice
quality also explains the appeal of the “It Gets Better” project, as it
challenges homophobic rhetoric by forcing its audience to see the real details
of GLBT lives. Even the tragic
suicides that inspired the project played a role in this
- there is absolutely nothing new about suicides caused by homophobic
bullying. However, having so many happen so close together - in a suddenly
socially-networked world – revealed an “old” narrative with new force.
11.
The fourth argument Livingston identifies supporting narrative is that narrative
is “crucial to psychology and related fields because the self or person has an
essentially narrative form, or because the self-concept requires storytelling,”
(Livingston, 26). I wonder if humans are prejudiced towards narratives in the
same way as we are prejudiced towards faces -
The phenomenon of pareidolia suggests that our visual system actively seeks to
find and recognize certain objects in the world. People across the world
consistently respond to pictures and other objects, even random patterns,
as if
they depict human faces or animals. Thus, artists can get away with ‘suggesting’
these specially perceived objects in their depictions, often with just a few
hints that suffice as cues
(Melcher & Bacci, 352)
- and whether we are prejudiced towards information that takes a narrative form
for the same reason.
This is why we have spokespeople and “Poster Children” for our causes.
A disease may be perceived as tragic, but when we see a television
commercial with a victim telling her story, we become more inclined to open our
wallets.
In the same way we prejudice information received in narrative form over raw
data such as lab results, we also tend to prejudice dramatic narratives over
straightforward ones- especially when these narrative concern ourselves.
For example, when Lewis leaves Mariah, but she becomes convinced that she
wanted him to leave. This is more of a case in prejudicing one narrative over
another than of prejudicing narrative in general,
but it is significant that the narrative Mariah chose is the one that
best supports her self-concept.
There was a narrative in which Lewis abandons her, and there was a narrative in
which he is banished. The banishment narrative has nobility and romance, and
seems a much richer story than that of the discarded wife. She recast Lewis's
desires into a story that disguised them as her own desires, and came to believe
that she wanted what she did not (Kincaid, 119).
12.
The fifth argument Livingston identifies supporting narrative is that narrative
is “potentially instructive because they represent general possibilities for
human lives,” (Livingston, 26).
This is the purpose for every myth, fable, and parable in human history. This is
why we love underdog stories. Most humans have a sense of their smallness in
relation the cosmos, the planet, and even their immediate community. Any time we
are exposed to a narrative in which an individual prevails against great odds,
we feel our own potential expanded. For such a narrative to have appeal, it has
to seem at least technically feasible. This means that if a story features and
outcome that theoretically could happen, it becomes a possibility for for
the reader. To a person
shipwrecked, the existence of such a novel as Robinson Crusoe may be the
only thing that keeps them going from day to day, despite how different the
facts of their story may be from Defoe's
13.
The sixth argument Livingston identifies supporting narrative is that narrative
is “the embodiment or expression of an otherwise ineffable wisdom,” (Livingston,
26). This is another feature of cultural stories, such as the parables of
Christ. Christ was bringing a very radical message to the people of Israel, and
what He was proposing was so unheard-of that He knew better than to approach it
head-on. The use of parables in His teaching was a more effective way to
communicate concepts such as humility (in the parable of the Pharisee and the
publican, for example). Jamaica Kincaid achieves this in an very different, but
incredibly elegant, manner, simply by writing A Small Place in the second
person (Kincaid, 257). For the
middle-class American or European reader, it is reflexive to resist the image of
oneself as the “incredibly unattractive, fat, and pastry-like fleshed” colonial
oppressor (Kincaid, 261). This image becomes ineffable, as the reader's refusal
to imagine himself in that role makes his complicity incommunicable. In using
the second person, Kincaid grabs the reader by his lapels and steamrolls over
this reluctance. This is a slight perversion of Goethe's
instruction to “treat him as if he were what
he ought to be,” in that, by treating him if he were what she believes him to
be, he will believe that too.
Conclusion:
Peter Brooks said “narrating is never innocent” (Brooks, 286). The experience of
peeking under the skirts of narrative, for me, has produced neither a “for” or
“against” opinion, but rather an understanding of the sublime -
as defined in the context of this seminar: both dreadful and hopeful; and
in the Burkian sense of that which terrifies and astonishes (Quinton, 72). It
has long been my personal observation that the human psyche prejudices
information that is received in story form over information received in
something like an encyclopedia entry, and I can see the potential for gross
manipulation in the seven arguments that Livingston identified “against”
narrative. The power is
astonishing, the potential is terrifying. Narrative is alchemical in that it can
work within the mind to transmute
questionable bases into unalloyed “facts,” which will be held all the more
tenaciously for having been planted there invisibly, under a cloak of
entertainment. These “facts” seem
to be organic - knowledge that has come to us through our own experience, and
any dry academic information that attempts to supplant them may never fully
succeed. The scariest part is that
the “facts” we create within each other are almost invariably about
each other. Our stories are overwhelmingly human stories, and the power of
narrative does most good when it serves to humanize an out-group so that we grow
to sympathize with them. There
terrifying part, however, is narrative's equal and opposite power to demonize,
instead.
Works Cited.
“Interview with Khushwant Singh.”
Mahfil 5. 1/2 (1968 –
1969): 27-42. JSTOR. Web 19 Oct. 2011
Achebe, Chinua. Things Fall Apart. Norton, New York:
2009.
Adéẹ̀kó, Adélékẹ̀. "Great Books Make Their Own History:
Things Fall Apart at
Fifty." Transition 100
(2008): 34-43.
JSTOR. Web. 30 Oct. 2011.
Aristotle.
The Poetics of Aristotle.
Macmillan, New York: 1898. Web. 6 Nov. 2011.
Brooks, Peter. “The Tale vs. The
Novel.” NOVEL: A Forum on Fiction
21.2/3 (1988): 285-292.
JSTOR. Web. 4 Nov. 2011.
Bruner, Jerome. “The Narrative
Construction of Reality.” Critical Inquiry
18 (1991): 1-21. JSTOR.
Web. 7 Nov. 2011.
Cavendish, Richard. "Birth Of Sir
James Brooke." History Today
53.4 (2003): 55. Academic Search Complete. Web. 6 Nov. 2011.
Chatman, Seymour. “What Can We Learn
from Contextualist Narratology?” Poetics Today
11.2
(1990): 309-328. JSTOR. Web. 4 Nov. 2011.
Conrad, Joseph.
Heart of Darkness and The Secret Sharer.
Penguin: New York: 1997.
Currie, Gregory. “Narrative
Representation and Causes.” The Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64.3 (2006): 309-316.
JSTOR. Web. 7 Nov. 2011. <
D'Augelli, Anthony R. Lesbians and Gay
men on Campus: Visibility, Empowerment, and Education.”
Peabody Journal of Education
66.3 (1989): 124-142. JSTOR. Web. 4 Nov. 2011.
experienceproject.com. “The Experience Project.”
Experience Project, Inc. 2004.
Web. 4 Nov. 2011
Kincaid, Jamaica. "A Small Place."
Touchstone anthology of contemporary creative
nonfiction: work
from 1970 to the present.
Williford, Lex and Martone, Michael. New York: Simon and Schuster,
207. 257-262.
Kincaid, Jamaica.
Lucy. Farrar Straus Giroux: New
York, 1990.
Livingston, Paisley. "Narrativity and
Knowledge." Journal of Aesthetics & Art Criticism
67.1 (2009): 25-36. Academic Search Complete. EBSCO. Web. 9 Oct. 2011.
Melcher, David, and Francesca Bacci.
"The visual system as a constraint on the survival and success of specific
artworks." Spatial Vision
21.3-5 (2008): 347-362. Academic Search Complete. EBSCO.
Web. 9 Oct. 2011.
Mukherjee, Bharati. Jasmine. Grove Weidenfiled: New York. 1989
Nichols, Jennifer J. "Poor Visitor":
Mobility as/of Voice in Jamaica Kincaid's Lucy."
MELUS 34.4
(2009): 187-207. JSTOR. Web 19 Oct. 2011.
Patterson, Keaton. “Self, Other, Us:
The Promise of Dialogue between Colonial and Postcolonial Texts.” Oct. 2, 2011.
Web. 4 Nov. 2011.
Peterson, Jessica. “Opposites React:
The Self-Other Relationship in Multicultural Literature.” Oct. 2,
2011. Web. 7 Nov. 2011.
Quinton, Anthone. “Burke on the
Sublime and Beautiful.” Philosophy
36.136 (1961): 71-73. JSTOR. Web. 30 Oct. 2011.
Samson, Melanie.“Towards a 'Friday'
Model of International Trade: A Feminist Deconstruction of Race and Gender Bias
in the Robinson Crusoe Trade Allegory.” The Canadian
Journal of Economics / Revue canadienne d'Economique
28.1 (1995). 143-158.
JSTOR. Web 19 Oct. 2011.
Velleman, J. David. “Narrative
Explanation.” The Philosophical Review
112.1 (2003): 1-25. JSTOR. Web. 6 Nov. 2011.
Wheeler, L. Kip. "Freytag's Pyramid."
Dr. Wheeler's Website. Carson-Newman
University. 26 Sept. 2011. Web. 4 Nov. 2011.
|