Helena Suess, The Unfamiliar: Epistemological Sublimity in
the American Gothic Genre
The United States
has stood for centuries as a metonym for ideologies of progress and
individualism, but Euro-American colonial roots to a large extent lie in the
country’s capacity as a wilderness refuge for anti-secular religious
communities. Even as “progress” ramped up through the Eighteenth and Nineteenth
Centuries, many Americans felt a profound disconnect from traditional knowledge
and valuation in the rational materialism and urban futurism of “enlightened”
selfhood and society. The Romantic literature of the American Renaissance, with
its thematic transcendence over quotidian life toward a nostalgic “return” to
idealized nature, offered an aesthetic resolution to this ideological paradox.
Very generally, American Romantic narrative relocates its “civilized” hero(es)
to a setting which, because “natural” as opposed to the hero’s “artificial”
environment, lacks familiar boundaries and rhythms (i.e.,
a priori knowledge of the
physical/metaphysical world). At first this place is strange and dangerous, but
the rules of nature steadily reveal themselves to the hero; if the hero absorbs
these rules and thus learns to experience natural danger not with fear and
repulsion but with awe and respect, Romantic space and lifestyle are revealed as
not only beautiful but preferable. Offered here is a quest both rational and
transcendent: the hero has the opportunity to align, by experience and
experiment (i.e., a posteriori
knowledge), with an ideology of naturalistic sublimity submitted as more
substantially “real” than the indifferent abstractions of civilization.[1] However,
the hero is not bound by any law besides that of the text itself to successfully
navigate the experiential trials through which one is to align with the
sublimity of Romantic life. The opportunity to learn does not mean the hero has
the capacity to integrate what is learned; what is offered as “real” may not
reveal any “rules” of itself that the hero can comprehend. The experience of the
unknown and unfamiliar, as it undermines the hero’s
a priori, may also endanger
psychological equilibrium. The hero may stumble into terrifying space both
physical and mental, not only unmapped but unmappable. Through four canonical
American Gothic tales—Hawthorne’s “Young Goodman Brown” and “The Minister’s
Black Veil,” and Poe’s “Ligeia” and “The Fall of the House of Usher”—this essay
will explore the Gothic genre’s restructuring of the Romantic telos of sublime
revelation. The revelatory arcs of these four stories lead, as in Romantic
fiction generally, toward a scene of transcendence over the ordinary and
familiar. But the Gothic mode threatens and even subverts the possibility of
ideological resolution. The transcendent moment occurs when the
a posteriori leads not away from but
toward repulsion, horror, insanity, “whatever is in any sort terrible.”[2]
The Gothic sublime thus maximizes its potential, not in simple confrontation
with awful unfamiliarity, but at the site of collapse of epistemological
boundaries where even the familiar becomes unfamiliar. “Young Goodman Brown” follows this arc exactly. Like the
other stories here treated, “Brown” can be recognized as of the Gothic genre by
its typifying of unfamiliar space as unsettling and claustrophobic (“the
gloomiest trees of the forest ... closed immediately behind”), illuminated by
vivid light/dark contrasts (“the strip of bright sky” barely penetrates “the
depth of gloom”), grotesque colors and figurations of the supernatural (“the
fire on the rock shot redly forth and formed a glowing arch above its base”).
Brown begins his story by taking leave of his (allegorical) wife Faith and his
familiar home of Salem village, to follow a path into dark and haunted woods
toward some “present evil purpose.” Almost immediately a quest in search of the
forbidden, whose completion demands departure from the safe and familiar, lies
in the narrative foreground. Allegorically, Brown’s progress toward something
new and different (sin and evil), away from traditional life (faith and
goodness), describes in broad strokes the pre-Twentieth Century Euro-American
ideological landscape. But for now the exact nature of Brown’s purpose is
obscure to the reader: this story will be one of revelation in the context of
conflicting ideologies. Brown guards himself against the moral malfeasance of his
journey by appealing to what he knows of the New England as the home of “people
of prayer, and good works.” On assurance of the spiritual fortitude in his
community including his wife, Brown stakes his own soul: after one night of
giving into temptation, he resolves, he will “cling to [Faith’s] skirts and
follow her to heaven.” But almost as soon as he enters the forest Brown faces a
man in the shape of his father, old Goodman Brown,” who immediately sets about
dismantling Brown’s familiar beliefs. Brown first learns of the secret cruelty
and sin of his ancestors, and of the man’s “very general acquaintance” with the
outwardly pious New England authorities. The man laughs when Brown poses the
righteousness of “that good old man, our minister.” A later interaction between
“old Goodman Brown” and Goody Cloyse, “a very pious and exemplary dame, who had
taught him [Brown] his catechism,” reveals that the man is in fact the devil,
while Cloyse herself goes to the meeting as an infanticidal witch. Stunned by the violence done on his beliefs by revelation,
Brown arrives at a site of epistemological arrest. Since entering the woods his
a priori has wrestled to absorb or
reject a posteriori, and the mental
strain prevents him from going further for the moment. He decides to return
home, but to do so he must first sit and recover through “pleasant and
praiseworthy meditations” on good conscience and respect for authority. As he
rests, however, a severe irony again attacks him with knowledge of unfamiliar
reality. He hears through the trees his lauded minister and “good old Deacon
Gookin” themselves going to the evil meeting, as they have apparently done many
times. Brown again experiences physically the epistemological assault, “ready to
sink down on the ground, faint and overburdened.” As he prays to heaven and
Faith (and faith) for their support he hears, from a “black mass of cloud”
emanating voices of “both saints and sinners,” the “uncertain sorrow” of his own
wife “entreating for some favor, which ... it would grieve her to obtain.” For
Brown this prodigy describes the capitulation of Faith/faith to temptation and
sin. Brown’s original ideological ground is overrun, it appears, and he
renounces all “good on earth.” His epistemological progress at least seems
complete: a posteriori has overcome
a priori and Brown has successfully
integrated into his reality the revelation that to the devil “is this world
given.” But this apparent epistemological transcendence—from old
“false” knowledge to new “truth”—is yet uncertain. The reader learns that Brown,
though now a “demoniac,” has not yet given up entirely the limitations of his
a priori. Brown arrives at the
meeting, a ceremony of sin attended by saints and criminals alike, but Faith is
absent. At this realization “hope came into his heart” that Faith/faith remains
somehow inviolate. Thus Brown reveals to the reader his persisting unwillingness
to accept the unfamiliar “truth” of evil’s power. When Faith herself appears as
Brown’s counterpart in sin, he yet remains terrified of revelation (“what
polluted wretches would the next glance show them [Brown and Faith] to each the
other!”). A complete transcendence to evil would have made evil familiar to
Brown and so guarded him against fears of further evil, as his naïveté had once
obscured moral bankruptcy. Instead Brown makes a final plea to Faith/faith,
interjecting his original displaced piety into the grotesquerie as he begs his
wife (and implicitly himself) to “resist the wicked one.” Suddenly Brown is alone in the woods. In this instant occurs
the story’s moment of epistemological sublimity. Here the boundaries of
knowledge collapse and leave Brown a “bewildered man” unable to separate fact
from fiction. Brown returns to Salem to find the town and Faith all as they
were, as if his a priori had never
been disturbed. But because of his experience Brown can no longer trust what
presents itself as knowable. Hawthorne calls even the reader’s comprehension
into question with a tease that suggests the entire narrative to this point was
“a wild dream.” The inability to organize and maintain clear epistemological
boundaries leaves Brown tortured by suspicion and fear until his “dying hour
[of] gloom.” Both faith and sin, tradition and progress, have proven to be
useless as ideologies capable of establishing truth: the one is willful
ignorance, the other secretive and ephemeral. Whereas in a typically Romantic story the hero might have
achieved a surer foundation for his faith and returned to the familiar world a
wiser man, “Brown” suggests the impossibility of reconciling oppositional
ideologies. “The Minister’s Black Veil” is rather more optimistic about
resolving a posteriori with
a priori,
despite its typically Gothic evocations of horror and gloom. But “Veil” is
no less invested than “Brown” in denaturing epistemological boundaries, though
it displaces the dialectic from the veiled Mr. Hooper, who appears on the scene
having already more or less successfully negotiated his epistemological
transcendence. In “Veil” it is not to Mr. Hooper but to his parishioners, and
with them the reader, that the sublime truth behind the veil is to be revealed. The
Romantic manifestation of the unfamiliar vis- However, the veil’s hold on the public imagination grants it
the ironic power of “making its wearer,” however much a “bugbear,” “a very
efficient clergyman.” Hooper himself ambiguously explains to his fiancée
Elizabeth that the veil is “a type and a symbol” of “sorrows dark enough” to
“separate [him] from the world.” But Hooper also asserts a kinship with “most
other mortals,” “enabled … to sympathize with all dark affections.”
Contextualized by the minister’s obsession with “secret sin,” the flimsy but
impermeable veil manifests the boundary between what is outwardly known and what
is inwardly concealed. As a result not any specific secret (Hooper’s own is only
hinted at, never revealed) but the existence of the secretive as such is
foregrounded throughout the tale. Faced with the veil, pious persons from “the
most innocent girl” to “the man of hardened breast” to government officials must
consciously confront their own “hoarded iniquity of thought and deed.” The
veil’s raison d’être is thus epistemological: it incites knowing. Milford’s
a priori is characteristically
repressive; its familiarity is sustained by prevention and ignorance of
challenges to the conventions of its faith ideology, in which expressed piety
essentializes a person as pious. But to conceptualize repression as the veil
does is to defamiliarize repression, to make repression ironically revelatory,
forcing the knowledge of repression as such. Milford’s
a posteriori thus arises in the
recognition that what is familiar is intrinsically unstable, as outward piety is
revealed to be the social expression not of inward piety but of deception. As a
Gothic story that turns on the interplay of repression and revelation, “Veil”
shares with “Brown” an epistemological activation of sublimity. The veil’s
significance at first baffles its would-be interpreters, but as Hooper’s
reputation grows and sinners come to recognize in him their own “mortal
anguish,” even strangers are “made to quake” at the inference of guilt concealed
by piety. Through the veil “the relation between
the signifier,” expressed piety, “and signified,” essential piety, “breaks down
and is replaced by an indeterminate relation” in which piety can be shown
to in fact signify hidden sin.[3]
Still, the sublimity of explicit revelation is deferred until the moment of
Hooper’s death. Refusing to remove his veil at the last, Hooper accuses all
humanity of “loathsomely treasuring up the secret of ... sin.” He declares his
vision that there lies “on every visage a Black Veil!” The obscurity of the
veil’s power is now unequivocal: sin is universal, and cannot be effaced except
by deliberate denial. Epistemological boundaries are revealed as willful and
arbitrary limitations on what is ideologically desirable, while ideology itself
is shown to be intrinsically paradoxical. Recoiling with “mutual affright” at
the sublimity of the revelation, the deathbed attendants overcome Reverend
Clark’s appeal to decorum and bury Hooper in the veil. Hooper’s final words deconstruct ideological axia, like
“Brown” submitting ideology as both reifying and arbitrary; his words beg the
question of how one is to cope with an unstable epistemology. The proffered
solutions in “Veil” are moralistic yet ironic, keeping in line with the
paradoxical nature of the problematic. (Hooper exposes and lives with/as the
contradiction, while his congregants continue to sublimate, with the severe
traditional piety of their “earliest ancestral sway,” the guilt obscured by
their original piety.) In the Poe stories concerning this essay, the
narrator-protagonists also experience sublimity as a moment of epistemological
breakdown; these narratives too demonstrate the destabilizing potential of
unfamiliar a posteriori.
But Poe’s tales differ in that their narrators, unlike Hawthorne’s seekers
of knowledge, are passive rather than active agents in their epistemological
progress. Brown sought new experience and made efforts to absorb it however
dangerous, while Milford’s citizens internalized the veil’s significance however
paradoxical. But Poe’s narrators pathologically resist
a posteriori, acquiring experience
only accidentally or obliquely and never willingly. They insist on the
essentiality of a priori against all
contrary evidence, their deliberate experiential inertia forcing epistemological
crises in which their narratives erupt in psychotic breaks from reality. Perhaps
it is for this reason as much as aesthetic effect that these stories end at the
transcendent moment itself without even as minimal and ambiguous a dénouement as
Goodman Brown’s. As repressive cases who lack even names to sustain their
existence (for convenience I shall call them “Poe”), the narrators have nowhere
to go once repression becomes untenable. In “The
Fall of the House of Usher” Poe appears on the scene experientially blank. His
arrival at the House is predicated on a summons whose purpose he does not
understand. He faces the House itself with “a sense of insufferable gloom” the
source of which he does not comprehend and can only articulate with vague
rationalistic suggestions of unpleasant “combinations of very simple natural
objects.” The reader learns nothing of Poe’s origins and history except as
concerns his relationship to Roderick Usher, which Poe ironically describes as
“intimate” in the same breath he admits to knowing “very little of my friend.”
Moreover the story’s reality, however frightening and ugly, at this point lacks
epistemological significance. The House itself is mundane however off-putting:
Poe is explicit about its lack of sublimity (“no goading of the imagination
could torture [the House] into aught of the sublime”). Both reader and Poe begin
with a priori empty save for the
assumption of materially limited reality.[4]
As such, progress through the story must be like Brown’s epistemological:
a posteriori must expand the limits
of knowledge for any action to
commence or resolution to be effected. The expansion of knowledge occurs for Poe almost as passively
as for the reader of his story. Poe learns “at intervals, and through broken and
equivocal hints” the secrets of Usher and the House. The purpose of the summons
is revealed to be nothing more than to comfort Roderick, who is obsessed with
“family evil” and his sister Madeline’s deadly illness, both of which Roderick
obscurely attributes to the House’s malign “sentience.” This comfort Poe
provides by distracting Roderick with books, music, painting, and other
aesthetic pursuits. In such activities Roderick provides sensory clues
(“perversions and amplifications” of music, paintings of “phantasmagoric
conceptions”) that he is in “full consciousness ... of the tottering of his
lofty reason.” Poe himself feels “creeping upon me ... [Roderick’s] wild
influences.” A posteriori here
undermines knowledge of rational reality. Like Goodman Brown, Poe is unable or unwilling to accept the
expansion of his familiar schema of knowledge to include supernatural
irrationalities like living houses and family curses. His rejection of
a posteriori anti-rationality is most
apparent in his single moment of attempted agency when, as Roderick (following
Madeline’s death) points to the “unnatural light” of the House’s sapience, Poe
responds by recourse to anxious repression. He tries to find a rational
explanation (“merely electrical phenomena”) for the “gaseous exhalation.”
Though he knows that Roderick is by now
so deteriorated that “ordinary occupations were neglected or forgotten,” Poe yet
tries to soothe Roderick by reading a book as if his friend was still disposed
to rational thought. But Roderick has “brought round his chair” so as to be
looking away toward the door. Poe is reading to himself as much as Roderick, to
distract himself from the imminent disruption of his familiar, non-sublime,
rationally ordered reality. Such an epistemology becomes ultimately indefensible
once Poe is faced with Madeline’s resurrection. Forced to accept as real an
event anathema to his a priori, Poe
becomes “aghast” and flees, turning only to watch the House explode into light,
fragment, and crumble into the tarn. Symbolically, this final scene describes
the breakdown of precariously ordered reality, accomplished by traumatic
defamiliarization of the limits of knowledge: an epistemological sublime. The epistemological orders of “Usher,” “Veil,” and “Brown,”
in which an organized and limited worldview is threatened by one expansive and
potentially chaotic, are reversed in “Ligeia,” though the sublime still plays
out at the boundary between known and unknown. This story begins with Poe fixed
in a hallucinatory and unreliable past. His first paragraph takes the reader
back through “long years” to reminisce on a love the object of which he by his
admission remembers with difficulty, save for hyperbolic abstractions of a
“beauty [that] passed into my spirit, there dwelling as in a shrine.” Poe’s
a priori here, rather than the
mundanity in “Usher,” is a Gothic
dreamscape of fantasy and desire centered on an otherworldly paramour described
as “the triumph of all things heavenly.” Throughout the story’s first half, the
reader is offered nothing definitive of Poe’s world besides Ligeia herself and
the impossible desires he shares with her: to attain “wisdom too divinely
precious not to be forbidden,” and for will to triumph over death. Ligeia
embodies a priori epistemology whose
limits reach beyond natural reality. Thus
Ligeia’s death effects a posteriori
in which the familiarly fantastic must submit to unfamiliar experience of
natural reality: the realization of Poe’s desires is blocked by traumatic
experience of mundanity. The story is suddenly relocated to a more material
world where realist details can penetrate the text, for instance the surname and
birthplace of Poe’s second wife Rowena, as contrasted with Ligeia’s obscure
origins. Whereas early in the story Gothicism arises in the context of Ligeia’s
Byronic ethereality, the style later is perpetuated through a lurid but
materialistic catalogue of the grotesque architecture and ornaments filling “the
gloomy and dreary grandeur” of the “castellated abbey.” A banal economic detail
even arises in Poe’s admission that the abbey was purchased with Ligeia’s money.
Mundane reality, however stylized, opposes the fantastic idealism of the story’s
first half. Poe’s desire to conform this reality to his ideal, to subvert
experience to desire, forces a sublime collapse of mundane possibility by the
story’s end.[5]
There are at
least two ways of reading the resurrection of Ligeia, but both point toward
sublime epistemological collapse, not only each reading on its own terms but as
one of several valid interpretations of the text. The first option is
tragicomic: Ligeia—with or without Poe’s psychic assistance—accomplishes her
resurrection through her will to live (i.e., her desire for life), murdering
Rowena from beyond the grave and inhabiting her body. Here reunion is effected
through chthonic manipulation of reality. The other reading is ironic.
“Ligeia’s” Poe is more substantially characterized than “Usher’s,” sufficiently
that the reader knows of his heavy opium usage and fragmentary memory. These
details, combined with Poe’s intense desire for Ligeia’s return and his
indifferent cruelty toward Rowena, may indicate that Poe himself murdered his
second wife and hallucinated Ligeia’s resurrection.[6]
Either reading, supernatural or criminal, reaches its climax where the fantasy
of desire intersects the reality of loss, where in a moment of sublimity the
delight of reunion commingles with horror at physical impossibility. This moment
is only possible when epistemology is shattered, when what is known to be false
becomes indistinguishable from truth—not only for the narrator but for the
reader, who experiences the sublime of “Ligeia” as the final parameter of an
interpretive riddle. All four of these stories indicate a preoccupation in the Gothic genre with the instability of certain knowing, and with the contradictions demanded of ideological alignment. To accept (or be born into) an ideology is to accept (or be born into) its epistemology, as a result to impose arbitrary limitations, powerful but inessential, on what one can know about reality. American Gothicism thus declines the teleology of American Romanticism generally, locating sublimity not in reconciliation or triumph one over the other of the powerful but oppositional American co-ideologies of tradition and progress, but in the anxiety of being caught in the defamiliarizing space between contradictory epistemologies. In this way the Gothic may anticipate by a half-century the Modernist aesthetic, which will eventually emerge in a complexified and socially destabilized West as the particular genre of self-conscious “unknowing.”[7] At the least, the Gothic establishes the epistemological criteria for modern horror, whose significant artists like Lovecraft and King will depend for their work’s effect on sublime fear of the spectacularly unfamiliar.
[1]
Throughout this essay I am assuming, broadly and without technical
justification, Foucauldian /Althusserian epistemology that asserts
knowledge is ideologically produced and reinforced but individually
internalized and activated; additionally, that knowledge determines
social and psychological reality. I am also assuming, in the case of
“The Minister’s Black Veil,” that the epistemologically unfamiliar
includes knowledge repressed in the unconscious as much as anything
“outside” ideology.
[2]
From Edmund Burke, A
Philosophical Inquiry into the Origins of Our Ideas of The Sublime and
the Beautiful (1757; rev. 1759), quoted on
LITR 5431: American Romanticism
course website. [3] Thomas Weiskel, The Romantic Sublime: Studies in the Structure and Psychology of Transcendence (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1976), ix. [4] The reader familiar with Poe may not have this assumption, but it is the epistemological starting point of the text itself, and thus of the reading experience as such.
[5]
This Poe is then perhaps somewhat more agential than “Usher’s,” in his
ironic attempt to positively enforce a proven negative, but if so then
he also undermines his own agency by making himself a passive observer
of Ligeia’s resurrection.
[6]
Again, Poe’s agency is suspect even in this interpretation, as textually
there is no sure indication that he has done anything of note in the
period following Ligeia’s death besides buy the abbey, marry again, and
dose himself with opium.
[7]
Cf. Philip M. Weinstein,
Unknowing: The Work of Modernist Fiction (
|