LITR 4370 TRAGEDY
Midterm2 Samples 2015

(midterm2 assignment)

Model Answers to Part 2.
Continue Learning about Tragedy Essay

Part 2. Learning about Tragedy 2: Revise, continue, improve, & Extend Essay begun in Midterm1 on learning experience with tragedy, extending to include Sophocles's Family of Oedipus plays. (Revise / improve midterm1 draft & add at least 5-7 paragraphs for 9-10 paragraph total.) 

Eric Anderson

Part Two: Staying Power: Comparing Ancient Tragedy and Comedy

            I entered this course with what I'd consider a strong grasp of American modernist tragedy and comedy but honest inexperience in the territory of ancient Greek drama and concomitant philosophy. A few months into the semester, I find myself making connections to books I have read using helpful critical stances borne out of the western groundwork laid by Aristotle, Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Nietzsche. Studying old tragedies and comedies throughout my undergrad career, I have come to the conclusion that tragedy holds up better over time. Senses of humor evolve and mutate year to year, not to mention century to century; and social climate necessitates unique reactionary comedy. On the other hand, tragedy remains largely fixed: what is sad and enigmatic in our time—death—is equally sad and enigmatic in Ancient Greece and all places through all times, and so interest in the genre persists and expands. This class has taught me that tragedy, to the exclusion of all its competitors, really is the profoundest genre.

            Comedy, already subjective to the beholder, is tough to pin down. Its essence, E.B. White explains, is such that it "has a certain fragility, an evasiveness" (qtd. in "Theories of Comedy"). According to Aristotle, "comedy is . . . an imitation of characters of a lower type" (Poetics, V). The audience does not empathize with these lower types because it does not see them as worthy reflections. Scrutinizing Agamemnon, I was immediately able to identify and differentiate between Apolline and the Dionysian traits despite my unfamiliarity with such a literary binary two months prior; however, I could not spot any great humor in the piece until Dr. White stepped in and provided context which explained that when the Watchman in the first part of The Oresteia relaxes on his "arms, just like a dog" (Aeschylus, 5), lowlier comic type is the implication. And I'm sure the author's coevals understood this. Centuries later, that simile merely strikes me as playful and salient, not necessarily comical, and the rift created by this misunderstanding is one main difference between comedy and tragedy and a reason why the former fades and the latter tends to survive longer as a genre: death and sadness require no such explanatory footnote. Some comedy, luckily, did strike a chord with me. Just as I was tickled by Chaucer's magnificent fart jokes in "the Miller's Tale", I am pleased to find out that ancient Greeks appreciated lewd humor, as proven by all the comical erections in Lysistrata (5.5; 5.79).

            The relative obscurity of the ribald comedy Lysistrata in the eyes of posterity is telling, though. Even among the most avid modern readers familiarity with Lysistrata is rare, whereas the average student is aware of the Oedipus tales, because the wider social consciousness retains that which it deems useful or notable. "To learn gives the liveliest pleasure " (Poetics, IV), and apart from the overly facile—if not completely futile—plea for love instead of war, and the mechanics and timing of mildly amusing puns which are the equivalence of lame parlor tricks (3.71; 4.26; 5.79), Lysistrata and all similarly raunchy comedies, offer little in the way of trusty precepts and divert minds away from contemplation of pressing issues. Lucky to survive as a dusty academic reference-point to ancient humor, it would be generous in the extreme to suggest much unique insight can be squeezed from Lysistrata past a certain point. Like most comedy, it simply delights rather than staggers, and thus its impact fades as new fancies earn our passing middle-minded attention. As a modern American, I can only hope that scholars two thousand from now will not be examining 21st century Adam Sandler films with the same anthropological curiosity and fervor. However, my experience in this class leads me to believe that, should his films somehow survive, future generations will be as baffled by and alienated from Sandler as any tasteful sane human is today. Always influenced by zeitgeist, comedy, in its particulars and eccentricities, soon becomes dated—too quaint to be as boundless as great ancient tragedy.

            Where comedy generally deals with inconsequential ephemeral matters, tragedy focuses on everlasting matters of life and death close-to-home. I can imagine and perhaps even live with the idea of murdering a hypothetical stranger or a far-off enemy; the distance either blunts emotion or provides jingoistic incentive; war romances thrive on this exact clear us versus them mentality. Good tragedies, however, writes Aristotle, "are founded on the stories of a few houses" (13c). Whether it is Oedipus committing accidental parricide, Agamemnon offering his daughter Iphigenia up to the gods, or Christine poisoning her husband Ezra, it is the intimacy between the killer and the killed that pushes the violence into the realm of unbearable calamity and "excite[s] pity and fear, this being the distinctive mark" (Poetics, XIII) of the greatest tragedy. Of course, I am repulsed by the prospect of killing anyone so close to my heart, so much so that pondering it too much hurts me and I must stop. 

            This is because tragedy entails perplexing suffering and forces humanity to confront the utter misery of life. We understand the humor in an erection or the sweetness of typical romantic lovers, but cannot so easily grasp the speculative mystery of intensities such Antigone's suicide, Oedipus and Jocasta's incest, or the internecine violence featured in The Oresteia. Instinctual self-preservation in mind, Jocasta begs Oedipus to stop "investigating" (Oedipus Rex, 1270) the true nature of his sordid past. She believes she "will suffer" (1271) if the truth is revealed. Like readers who bristle at tragedy or reject it completely, she recognizes the magnitude of the emotion she would have to endure. People in this stubborn camp refuse that to grow—or in Aristotelian terms undergo the great pleasure of learning—are self-consigned to incomplete, lukewarm existences. Elderly, returned from exile, veteran of grief, blind and wise like Tiresias, Oedipus, expressing the taxing intended effect of tragedy, impresses upon his daughter Antigone that he is "taught by suffering" (Oedipus at Colonus, 5). Once an unwilling participant, has evolved and embraced painful nuance. Having tracked the struggles of Oedipus and felt the characteristic fear and pity best provoked by tragic circumstance , I now better appreciate the humble transformative trauma of learning.

            The main characters of tragedy seize our prolonged attention because in them is the vigorous representation of human complexity. Comic and romantic figures fit into clearly demarcated tropes: there's the jolly fat guy and his hyperactive small friend, the dashing hunk and the beautiful small-town girl. But in tragedy "no mortal man is ever blessed" (Oedipus Rex, 1431), and the stakes are hardly so simple. Standing quite apart, tragic figures defy easy classification and present more realistic psyches. In his Nobel Prize acceptance speech, modernist tragic novelist William Faulkner—who, following in the footsteps of Aeschylus, Shakespeare and the rest, inflicted classic familial agony on the Compsons, Snopeses, and Sutpens, to name a few clans—claims that the only topic truly worth writing about is "the human heart in conflict with itself". Tragic figures either make tough internal decisions or are subjected to tough internal suffering regardless of choice. When Agamemnon, caught in that selfsame conflict of the heart, sacrifices his daughter, he is not taking up the plain mantle of villainy; he is ensuring the survival of his people by gaining favorable traveling winds from the gods. Antigone, rebuffed at every turn by tradition and orders from her superiors, forsakes sedately observed division of right and wrong when she illegally buries her slain brother Polynices. In the aftermath, she complies with law's procedure, having transcended boundaries. Even the lowly guard, used to thinking in simple binaries, recognizes the tender balance Antigone has struck, claiming: "it's a joy / escaping troubles which affect oneself, / but painful to bring evil on one's friends" (Antigone, 493-5). However, "tragedy does not always have to be dark" (Hollen), as epitomized by Antigone's brave rebellion and again by the restoration of peace and order in the final part of The Oresteia. External forces may warrant curiosity, but externality causes disengagement which disincentives the introspection tragedy aims to provoke. Certainly complex and perhaps unpalatable, tragedy makes the audience contemplate the singular inward potential for both good and evil (Antigone, 417).

            Another reason tragedy survives is the larger-than-life characters whom the audience deem worthy of imitation and respect. The audience seeks improvement in mirroring the behavior of the heroes since they are depicted as "better than in actual life" (Poetics, II). Given the opportunity, we would rather become stately, influential, brave, and noble—like Oedipus, Antigone, Agamemnon, and Orestes—than aloof, lowly, and undignified—like the forgettable Watchman in Agamemnon or the galling jokesters in Lysistrata. Suffering admirably against all odds, acting beyond insular self-interest, representative of society's values, tragic heroes, warts and all, gain reputations as eminent synecdoches. Their stories register with us, packing the varied enigmatic punch known as catharsis. We "feel an enlargement before great or good work, an expansion," explains the renowned poet William Carlos Williams, because "it gives the feeling of completion by revealing the oneness of experience" (The Collected Poems, 194). While entertaining to an extent, comedic and romantic figures, rather than prompt growth and essential illumination, reinforce unadventurous preconceptions. Aristotle would no doubt agree that great tragic figures "rouse rather than stupefy the intelligence" (Williams, 194).

            Death, the focus of tragedy and the universal end which we all share, remains an obsession to this day. Humanity can neither solve it nor get shut of it. A persistent mystery, it triggers the extremest pity and fear. Learning being the greatest pleasure, we are denied by death because it does not divulge its secrets. Antigone hangs herself, and thousand plus years later Hamlet is still asking the most fundamental question: "To be or not to be" (Shakespeare, 3.1.58). The morbid curiosity furthermore reverberates into the 20th century. Eugene O'Neill's drama Mourning Becomes Electra is nothing if not an American modernization of the classics written by Aeschylus. Then there's William Faulkner's novel Absalom, Absalom!, a tragedy wherein a suicidal daughter significantly named Clytemnestra is just one of the doomed branches on the Sutpen family tree. Along with cultivated interest in the Greek classics and these updates, we have an indication: a desperate attempt to grasp the enormity of life and death. Where comedy recedes into a cultural oddity, tragedy precludes any reduction of gravity.                                                     

            We flock towards comedy as comforting temporary respite from the truth. We indulge in romance because we wish a narrative so agreeable and clear-cut could replace the truth. We initially shy away from tragedy because it refuses to sugarcoat the brutal truth, but come to learn that it presents humanity for what it really is, both triumphant and piteous. The frustration, the very irreducibility of universal and inscrutable themes, is precisely what makes it a worthwhile object of study. Tragically, tragedy is here to stay.